翻訳と辞書
Words near each other
・ Relative rate test
・ Relative Record Data Set
・ Relative return
・ Relative risk
・ Relative risk reduction
・ Relative scalar
・ Relative Silence
・ Relative species abundance
・ Relative Strangers
・ Relative strength
・ Relative strength index
・ Relative survival
・ Relative term
・ Relative thermal resistance
・ Relative transmission level
Relative utilitarianism
・ Relative validity
・ Relative valuation
・ Relative value
・ Relative value (economics)
・ Relative value unit
・ Relative Values
・ Relative Values (film)
・ Relative Values (play)
・ Relative velocity
・ Relative viscosity
・ Relative volatility
・ Relative Ways
・ Relative wind
・ Relatively compact subspace


Dictionary Lists
翻訳と辞書 辞書検索 [ 開発暫定版 ]
スポンサード リンク

Relative utilitarianism : ウィキペディア英語版
Relative utilitarianism

Let X be a set of possible `states of the world' or `alternatives'; society wishes to choose some state from X. Let I be a finite set, representing a collection of people. For each i \in I, let u_i:X\longrightarrow\mathbb be a ''utility function''. A ''social choice rule'' (or ''voting system'') is a mechanism which uses the data (u_i)_ to select some element(s) from X which are `best' for society. (The basic problem of social choice theory is to disambiguate the word `best'.)
The classic utilitarian social choice rule selects the element x \in X which maximizes the ''utilitarian sum''
U(x):= \sum_ u_i(x).

However, for this formula to make sense, we must assume that the utility functions (u_i)_ are both cardinal, and interpersonally comparable at a cardinal level.
The notion that individuals have cardinal utility functions is not that problematic. Cardinal utility has been implicitly assumed in decision theory ever since Daniel Bernoulli's analysis of the Saint Petersburg Paradox. Rigorous mathematical theories of cardinal utility (with application to risky decision making) were developed by Frank P. Ramsey, Bruno de Finetti,
von Neumann and Morgenstern, and Leonard Savage. However, in these theories, a person's utility function is only well-defined up to an `affine rescaling'. Thus, if the utility function u_i:X\longrightarrow \mathbb is valid description of her preferences, and if r_i,s_i\in \mathbb are two constants with s_i>0, then the `rescaled' utility function v_i(x) := s_i\, u_i(x) + r_i is an equally valid description of her preferences. If we define a new package of utility functions (v_i)_ using possibly different r_i\in \mathbb and s_i>0 for all i \in I, and we then consider the utilitarian sum
V(x):= \sum_ v_i(x),

then in general, the maximizer of V will ''not'' be the same as the maximizer of U. Thus, in a sense, classic utilitarian social choice is not well-defined within the standard model of cardinal utility used in decision theory, unless we specify some mechanism to `calibrate' the utility functions of the different individuals.
''Relative utilitarianism'' proposes a natural calibration mechanism. For every i \in I , suppose that the values
m_i \ := \ \min_ \, u_i(x) \quad \mbox\quad M_i \ := \ \max_ \, u_i(x)

are well-defined. (For example, this will always be true if X is finite, or if X is a compact space and u_i is a continuous function.) Then define
w_i(x) \ := \ \frac

for all x\in X. Thus, w_i:X \longrightarrow \mathbb is a `rescaled' utility function which has a minimum value of 0 and a maximum value of 1. The Relative Utilitarian social choice rule selects the element in X which maximizes the utilitarian sum
W(x):= \sum_ w_i(x).

As an abstract social choice function, relative utilitarianism has been analyzed by Cao (1982), Dhillon (1998), Karni (1998), Dhillon and Mertens (1999), Segal (2000), Sobel (2001) and Pivato (2008). (Cao (1982) refers to it as the `modified Thomson solution'.) When interpreted as a `voting rule', it is equivalent to Range voting.
== See also ==

*Range voting

抄文引用元・出典: フリー百科事典『 ウィキペディア(Wikipedia)
ウィキペディアで「Relative utilitarianism」の詳細全文を読む



スポンサード リンク
翻訳と辞書 : 翻訳のためのインターネットリソース

Copyright(C) kotoba.ne.jp 1997-2016. All Rights Reserved.